低压高吃什么药最有效| 为什么大便会拉出血| peppa是什么意思| 月经结束一周后又出血是什么原因| 熟的反义词是什么| 鼻窦炎挂什么科| 永浴爱河是什么意思| 精益求精的意思是什么| 7月14日什么星座| 女人吃什么补气血效果最好| 为什么半夜流鼻血| 做梦掉牙齿是什么意思周公解梦| 什么舌头| 嘴里发甜是什么原因| 皮脂膜是什么| 5月11号是什么星座| 四季豆为什么叫四季豆| 车水马龙是什么意思| 力排众议是什么意思| 办离婚需要什么手续和证件| 02年属马的是什么命| 医学ace是什么意思| 手肿是什么原因引起的| sobranie是什么烟| 牙齿酸软是什么原因| 武夷山在什么地方| 狗狗细小是什么症状| 不知所云是什么意思| 什么是应力| 黄豆酱做什么菜好吃| 头秃了一块是什么原因| 农历五月初五是什么节日| 七月十九是什么星座| 吃什么排铜最快| 乳清是什么| 埋线是什么| 夏天适合吃什么菜| 低血压吃什么可以补| 你喜欢我什么我改| 荔枝什么品种最贵| 什么食物去湿气效果好| 扶她是什么| 臭屁是什么意思| 甲沟炎用什么药好| 纯天然无公害什么意思| 情窦初开是什么意思| 在下是什么意思| ab血型和o血型的孩子是什么血型| 喝什么水减肥最快| 一个提手一个京念什么| 蜘蛛的血液是什么颜色| 啤酒ipa是什么意思| 唇炎看什么科室| 嫂嫂是什么意思| 喝酒脸红是什么原因造成的| 墨镜镜片什么材质好| mio是什么意思| 甲钴胺治疗什么病| iwc是什么牌子手表| 咳嗽吃什么食物好得最快最有效| 女生痛经有什么办法缓解| 开化龙顶属于什么茶| 利血平是什么药| 武汉大学校长是什么级别| 什么是快闪| 阿莫西林主要治疗什么| 大头虾是什么意思| 尿中红细胞高是什么原因| 全身酸痛失眠什么原因| 中暑喝什么| 胃气上逆是什么原因造成的| 吃什么补精| 什么汤好喝又简单| 放疗什么意思| 42岁属什么| 乳糖不耐受吃什么药| 为什么地球是圆的| 梦到羊是什么意思| 84年什么命| 为什么新疆人不吃猪肉| 月经期间喝酒会有什么影响| 五脏六腑是什么意思| 汗疱疹擦什么药| 七情六欲指的是什么| 木姜子是什么东西| 嘴干是什么病的征兆| 嘴角上方有痣代表什么| 喉咙发痒咳嗽吃什么药| 推迟月经吃什么药| 血栓弹力图是查什么的| 7.14号是什么节日| 脾围是什么意思| 牛叉是什么意思| 9月25日是什么星座| 牟作为姓氏时读什么| 什么药对伤口愈合快| 桥本甲状腺炎吃什么药| 腹部b超挂什么科| 优柔寡断是什么意思| 兰花用什么肥料最好| 笑对人生是什么意思| 中药一剂是什么意思| 为什么会长汗斑| 玫瑰花有什么作用| 龙的九个儿子都叫什么名字| 犬吠是什么意思| 桃子什么季节成熟| 相向是什么意思| 参保是什么意思| 智字五行属什么| 中药吃多了对人体有什么伤害| 大便发黑是什么情况| 什么什么什么花的成语| 阴道内痒是什么原因| 早上六点是什么时辰| 抖是什么生肖| 二月出生是什么星座| 哺乳期可以吃什么感冒药| 哥文花园女装什么档次| 大姨妈量少什么原因| 喉炎是什么原因引起的| 尿频尿急尿不尽吃什么药最快见效| 皮肤黄吃什么可以改善| 梦见和老公结婚是什么意思| 去湿气吃什么最好| 民营企业和私营企业有什么区别| 真菌孢子阳性什么意思| 木薯淀粉可以做什么| 法国的国花是什么花| 53年属什么| 咪咪头疼是什么原因| 鸿运当头什么意思| 属鼠适合佩戴什么饰品| 为什么会长闭口粉刺| 尿道发炎吃什么药| 血铅是什么| m代表什么意思| 白天不咳嗽晚上咳嗽是什么原因| 凝血五项是检查什么病| 红馆是什么地方| 小狗拉肚子吃什么药| 朱元璋原名叫什么| 中国文字博大精深什么意思| 牙合是什么字| 八一建军节什么生肖| 海纳百川是什么意思| 心率低有什么危害| 588是什么意思| 随喜赞叹是什么意思| power是什么牌子| 走私是什么| 檀木手串有什么好处| 腋下副乳有什么危害吗| 菩提树长什么样| 和珅属什么生肖| 奶篓子是什么意思| vt是什么意思| 肺脓肿是什么病严重吗| 蛋白粉和胶原蛋白粉有什么区别| 情妇是什么意思| 什么叫湿气| 看得什么| 下海的意思是什么| 告加鸟念什么| 香港有什么东西值得买| 心不在焉什么意思| iwc是什么牌子手表| 35岁属什么生肖| 碱面是什么| 什么牌子的洗衣机最好| 人体有365个什么| 四十岁月经量少是什么原因| 口臭胃火大吃什么药好| 血小板减少是什么病| 6是什么意思| 乐话提醒业务是什么意思| 521是什么星座的| 借什么不用还| 螨虫用什么药膏| 魂牵梦萦的意思是什么| 丙肝阳性是什么意思呢| 血糖看什么指标| 早上五点是什么时辰| 什么叫2型糖尿病| 白癜风是什么原因引起的| 刘彻是刘邦的什么人| 自然是什么意思| 巳时是什么时间| 西瓜和什么食物相克| 胃药吃多了有什么副作用| 日本豆腐是什么材料| 黄瓜苦是什么原因| 碱吃多了有什么危害| 撒尿分叉是什么原因| 柠檬水有什么功效| 脸上不停的长痘痘是什么原因| 岁月如梭是什么意思| 化疗后恶心呕吐吃什么可以缓解| 咽拭子是检查什么的| 手麻是什么病| 吃菱角有什么好处| 矫正是什么意思| 提辖相当于现在什么官| 幅度是什么意思| 钵钵鸡是什么| 蛋白粉吃了有什么好处| 左眼皮跳是什么原因| 什么是个体工商户| 反流性食管炎能吃什么水果| 顺其自然是什么意思| 后装治疗是什么意思| 腹泻是什么原因引起的| 边界清是什么意思| 长得什么| 肾结石吃什么水果好| dave是什么意思| 免疫力和抵抗力有什么区别| 吃什么蛋白质含量最高| 为什么太阳会发光| 肠镜什么情况下取活检| 甲苯是什么| 特别出演什么意思| 和南圣众是什么意思| 家里为什么会有隐翅虫| 时点是什么意思| 游走性疼痛挂什么科| 中央电视台台长是什么级别| 骨瘤是什么病| 肚子胀恶心想吐是什么原因| 牙套什么年龄戴合适| 初检检查什么| 摩羯座什么时候| 培根是什么肉做的| 95511是什么号码| 运动后体重增加是什么原因| 良善是什么意思| 婴儿泡奶粉用什么水好| 腰腿疼痛吃什么药效果好| 球蛋白偏低是什么意思| 割包皮是什么意思| 左心房增大是什么原因| 画像是什么意思| 甲状腺不均质改变是什么意思| 什么方法睡觉快速入睡| 胃疼吃什么药最管用| 乳腺增生挂什么科| 什么药| 黄连泡水喝有什么功效| 火影忍者大结局是什么| 紫罗兰色是什么颜色| ber是什么意思| 接风是什么意思| 胃发热是什么原因| 脚后跟开裂是什么原因| 肺部结节是什么意思啊| 中意你是什么意思| 医生为什么看瞳孔知道没救了| 流氓是什么意思| 安是什么生肖| 孕妇低血压什么补最快| 刺猬是什么动物| 为什么一吃辣的就拉肚子| 额头炎是什么症状| 吃什么减肥| 百度Jump to content

车讯:即日开启预售 江淮瑞风S1更名为S2 mini

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 实施绿色制造工程,推动工业资源全面节约和循环利用,积极发展绿色金融,实现生产系统和生活系统循环链接。

Computability theory, also known as recursion theory, is a branch of mathematical logic, computer science, and the theory of computation that originated in the 1930s with the study of computable functions and Turing degrees. The field has since expanded to include the study of generalized computability and definability. In these areas, computability theory overlaps with proof theory and effective descriptive set theory.

Basic questions addressed by computability theory include:

  • What does it mean for a function on the natural numbers to be computable?
  • How can noncomputable functions be classified into a hierarchy based on their level of noncomputability?

Although there is considerable overlap in terms of knowledge and methods, mathematical computability theorists study the theory of relative computability, reducibility notions, and degree structures; those in the computer science field focus on the theory of subrecursive hierarchies, formal methods, and formal languages. The study of which mathematical constructions can be effectively performed is sometimes called recursive mathematics.[a]

Introduction

[edit]

n 2 3 4 5 6 7 ...
Σ(n) 4 6 13 4098 > 3.5×1018267 > 1010101018705353 ?
Does not appear The Busy Beaver function Σ(n) grows faster than any computable function.
Hence, it is not computable;[2] only a few values are known.

Computability theory originated in the 1930s, with the work of Kurt G?del, Alonzo Church, Rózsa Péter, Alan Turing, Stephen Kleene, and Emil Post.[3][b]

The fundamental results the researchers obtained established Turing computability as the correct formalization of the informal idea of effective calculation. In 1952, these results led Kleene to coin the two names "Church's thesis"[4]:?300? and "Turing's thesis".[4]:?376? Nowadays these are often considered as a single hypothesis, the Church–Turing thesis, which states that any function that is computable by an algorithm is a computable function. Although initially skeptical, by 1946 G?del argued in favor of this thesis:[5]:?84?

"Tarski has stressed in his lecture (and I think justly) the great importance of the concept of general recursiveness (or Turing's computability). It seems to me that this importance is largely due to the fact that with this concept one has for the first time succeeded in giving an absolute notion to an interesting epistemological notion, i.e., one not depending on the formalism chosen."[5]:?84?[6]

With a definition of effective calculation came the first proofs that there are problems in mathematics that cannot be effectively decided. In 1936, Church[7][8] and Turing[9] were inspired by techniques used by G?del to prove his incompleteness theorems - in 1931, G?del independently demonstrated that the Entscheidungsproblem is not effectively decidable. This result showed that there is no algorithmic procedure that can correctly decide whether arbitrary mathematical propositions are true or false.

Many problems in mathematics have been shown to be undecidable after these initial examples were established.[c] In 1947, Markov and Post published independent papers showing that the word problem for semigroups cannot be effectively decided. Extending this result, Pyotr Novikov and William Boone showed independently in the 1950s that the word problem for groups is not effectively solvable: there is no effective procedure that, given a word in a finitely presented group, will decide whether the element represented by the word is the identity element of the group. In 1970, Yuri Matiyasevich proved (using results of Julia Robinson) Matiyasevich's theorem, which implies that Hilbert's tenth problem has no effective solution; this problem asked whether there is an effective procedure to decide whether a Diophantine equation over the integers has a solution in the integers.

Turing computability

[edit]

The main form of computability studied in the field was introduced by Turing in 1936.[9] A set of natural numbers is said to be a computable set (also called a decidable, recursive, or Turing computable set) if there is a Turing machine that, given a number n, halts with output 1 if n is in the set and halts with output 0 if n is not in the set. A function f from natural numbers to natural numbers is a (Turing) computable, or recursive function if there is a Turing machine that, on input n, halts and returns output f(n). The use of Turing machines here is not necessary; there are many other models of computation that have the same computing power as Turing machines; for example the μ-recursive functions obtained from primitive recursion and the μ operator.

The terminology for computable functions and sets is not completely standardized. The definition in terms of μ-recursive functions as well as a different definition of rekursiv functions by G?del led to the traditional name recursive for sets and functions computable by a Turing machine. The word decidable stems from the German word Entscheidungsproblem which was used in the original papers of Turing and others. In contemporary use, the term "computable function" has various definitions: according to Nigel J. Cutland,[10] it is a partial recursive function (which can be undefined for some inputs), while according to Robert I. Soare[11] it is a total recursive (equivalently, general recursive) function. This article follows the second of these conventions. In 1996, Soare[12] gave additional comments about the terminology.

Not every set of natural numbers is computable. The halting problem, which is the set of (descriptions of) Turing machines that halt on input 0, is a well-known example of a noncomputable set. The existence of many noncomputable sets follows from the facts that there are only countably many Turing machines, and thus only countably many computable sets, but according to the Cantor's theorem, there are uncountably many sets of natural numbers.

Although the halting problem is not computable, it is possible to simulate program execution and produce an infinite list of the programs that do halt. Thus the halting problem is an example of a computably enumerable (c.e.) set, which is a set that can be enumerated by a Turing machine (other terms for computably enumerable include recursively enumerable and semidecidable). Equivalently, a set is c.e. if and only if it is the range of some computable function. The c.e. sets, although not decidable in general, have been studied in detail in computability theory.

Areas of research

[edit]

Beginning with the theory of computable sets and functions described above, the field of computability theory has grown to include the study of many closely related topics. These are not independent areas of research: each of these areas draws ideas and results from the others, and most computability theorists are familiar with the majority of them.

Relative computability and the Turing degrees

[edit]

Computability theory in mathematical logic has traditionally focused on relative computability, a generalization of Turing computability defined using oracle Turing machines, introduced by Turing in 1939.[13] An oracle Turing machine is a hypothetical device which, in addition to performing the actions of a regular Turing machine, is able to ask questions of an oracle, which is a particular set of natural numbers. The oracle machine may only ask questions of the form "Is n in the oracle set?". Each question will be immediately answered correctly, even if the oracle set is not computable. Thus an oracle machine with a noncomputable oracle will be able to compute sets that a Turing machine without an oracle cannot.

Informally, a set of natural numbers A is Turing reducible to a set B if there is an oracle machine that correctly tells whether numbers are in A when run with B as the oracle set (in this case, the set A is also said to be (relatively) computable from B and recursive in B). If a set A is Turing reducible to a set B and B is Turing reducible to A then the sets are said to have the same Turing degree (also called degree of unsolvability). The Turing degree of a set gives a precise measure of how uncomputable the set is.

The natural examples of sets that are not computable, including many different sets that encode variants of the halting problem, have two properties in common:

  1. They are computably enumerable, and
  2. Each can be translated into any other via a many-one reduction. That is, given such sets A and B, there is a total computable function f such that A = {x : f(x) ∈ B}. These sets are said to be many-one equivalent (or m-equivalent).

Many-one reductions are "stronger" than Turing reductions: if a set A is many-one reducible to a set B, then A is Turing reducible to B, but the converse does not always hold. Although the natural examples of noncomputable sets are all many-one equivalent, it is possible to construct computably enumerable sets A and B such that A is Turing reducible to B but not many-one reducible to B. It can be shown that every computably enumerable set is many-one reducible to the halting problem, and thus the halting problem is the most complicated computably enumerable set with respect to many-one reducibility and with respect to Turing reducibility. In 1944, Post[14] asked whether every computably enumerable set is either computable or Turing equivalent to the halting problem, that is, whether there is no computably enumerable set with a Turing degree intermediate between those two.

As intermediate results, Post defined natural types of computably enumerable sets like the simple, hypersimple and hyperhypersimple sets. Post showed that these sets are strictly between the computable sets and the halting problem with respect to many-one reducibility. Post also showed that some of them are strictly intermediate under other reducibility notions stronger than Turing reducibility. But Post left open the main problem of the existence of computably enumerable sets of intermediate Turing degree; this problem became known as Post's problem. After ten years, Kleene and Post showed in 1954 that there are intermediate Turing degrees between those of the computable sets and the halting problem, but they failed to show that any of these degrees contains a computably enumerable set. Very soon after this, Friedberg and Muchnik independently solved Post's problem by establishing the existence of computably enumerable sets of intermediate degree. This groundbreaking result opened a wide study of the Turing degrees of the computably enumerable sets which turned out to possess a very complicated and non-trivial structure.

There are uncountably many sets that are not computably enumerable, and the investigation of the Turing degrees of all sets is as central in computability theory as the investigation of the computably enumerable Turing degrees. Many degrees with special properties were constructed: hyperimmune-free degrees where every function computable relative to that degree is majorized by a (unrelativized) computable function; high degrees relative to which one can compute a function f which dominates every computable function g in the sense that there is a constant c depending on g such that g(x) < f(x) for all x > c; random degrees containing algorithmically random sets; 1-generic degrees of 1-generic sets; and the degrees below the halting problem of limit-computable sets.

The study of arbitrary (not necessarily computably enumerable) Turing degrees involves the study of the Turing jump. Given a set A, the Turing jump of A is a set of natural numbers encoding a solution to the halting problem for oracle Turing machines running with oracle A. The Turing jump of any set is always of higher Turing degree than the original set, and a theorem of Friedburg shows that any set that computes the Halting problem can be obtained as the Turing jump of another set. Post's theorem establishes a close relationship between the Turing jump operation and the arithmetical hierarchy, which is a classification of certain subsets of the natural numbers based on their definability in arithmetic.

Much recent research on Turing degrees has focused on the overall structure of the set of Turing degrees and the set of Turing degrees containing computably enumerable sets. A deep theorem of Shore and Slaman[15] states that the function mapping a degree x to the degree of its Turing jump is definable in the partial order of the Turing degrees. A survey by Ambos-Spies and Fejer[16] gives an overview of this research and its historical progression.

Other reducibilities

[edit]

An ongoing area of research in computability theory studies reducibility relations other than Turing reducibility. Post[14] introduced several strong reducibilities, so named because they imply truth-table reducibility. A Turing machine implementing a strong reducibility will compute a total function regardless of which oracle it is presented with. Weak reducibilities are those where a reduction process may not terminate for all oracles; Turing reducibility is one example.

The strong reducibilities include:

One-one reducibility: A is one-one reducible (or 1-reducible) to B if there is a total computable injective function f such that each n is in A if and only if f(n) is in B.
Many-one reducibility: This is essentially one-one reducibility without the constraint that f be injective. A is many-one reducible (or m-reducible) to B if there is a total computable function f such that each n is in A if and only if f(n) is in B.
Truth-table reducibility: A is truth-table reducible to B if A is Turing reducible to B via an oracle Turing machine that computes a total function regardless of the oracle it is given. Because of compactness of Cantor space, this is equivalent to saying that the reduction presents a single list of questions (depending only on the input) to the oracle simultaneously, and then having seen their answers is able to produce an output without asking additional questions regardless of the oracle's answer to the initial queries. Many variants of truth-table reducibility have also been studied.

Further reducibilities (positive, disjunctive, conjunctive, linear and their weak and bounded versions) are discussed in the article Reduction (computability theory).

The major research on strong reducibilities has been to compare their theories, both for the class of all computably enumerable sets as well as for the class of all subsets of the natural numbers. Furthermore, the relations between the reducibilities has been studied. For example, it is known that every Turing degree is either a truth-table degree or is the union of infinitely many truth-table degrees.

Reducibilities weaker than Turing reducibility (that is, reducibilities that are implied by Turing reducibility) have also been studied. The most well known are arithmetical reducibility and hyperarithmetical reducibility. These reducibilities are closely connected to definability over the standard model of arithmetic.

Rice's theorem and the arithmetical hierarchy

[edit]

Rice showed that for every nontrivial class C (which contains some but not all c.e. sets) the index set E = {e: the eth c.e. set We is in C} has the property that either the halting problem or its complement is many-one reducible to E, that is, can be mapped using a many-one reduction to E (see Rice's theorem for more detail). But, many of these index sets are even more complicated than the halting problem. These type of sets can be classified using the arithmetical hierarchy. For example, the index set FIN of the class of all finite sets is on the level Σ2, the index set REC of the class of all recursive sets is on the level Σ3, the index set COFIN of all cofinite sets is also on the level Σ3 and the index set COMP of the class of all Turing-complete sets Σ4. These hierarchy levels are defined inductively, Σn+1 contains just all sets which are computably enumerable relative to Σn; Σ1 contains the computably enumerable sets. The index sets given here are even complete for their levels, that is, all the sets in these levels can be many-one reduced to the given index sets.

Reverse mathematics

[edit]

The program of reverse mathematics asks which set-existence axioms are necessary to prove particular theorems of mathematics in subsystems of second-order arithmetic. This study was initiated by Harvey Friedman and was studied in detail by Stephen Simpson and others; in 1999, Simpson[17] gave a detailed discussion of the program. The set-existence axioms in question correspond informally to axioms saying that the powerset of the natural numbers is closed under various reducibility notions. The weakest such axiom studied in reverse mathematics is recursive comprehension, which states that the powerset of the naturals is closed under Turing reducibility.

Numberings

[edit]

A numbering is an enumeration of functions; it has two parameters, e and x and outputs the value of the e-th function in the numbering on the input x. Numberings can be partial-computable although some of its members are total computable functions. Admissible numberings are those into which all others can be translated. A Friedberg numbering (named after its discoverer) is a one-one numbering of all partial-computable functions; it is necessarily not an admissible numbering. Later research dealt also with numberings of other classes like classes of computably enumerable sets. Goncharov discovered for example a class of computably enumerable sets for which the numberings fall into exactly two classes with respect to computable isomorphisms.

The priority method

[edit]

Post's problem was solved with a method called the priority method; a proof using this method is called a priority argument. This method is primarily used to construct computably enumerable sets with particular properties. To use this method, the desired properties of the set to be constructed are broken up into an infinite list of goals, known as requirements, so that satisfying all the requirements will cause the set constructed to have the desired properties. Each requirement is assigned to a natural number representing the priority of the requirement; so 0 is assigned to the most important priority, 1 to the second most important, and so on. The set is then constructed in stages, each stage attempting to satisfy one of more of the requirements by either adding numbers to the set or banning numbers from the set so that the final set will satisfy the requirement. It may happen that satisfying one requirement will cause another to become unsatisfied; the priority order is used to decide what to do in such an event.

Priority arguments have been employed to solve many problems in computability theory, and have been classified into a hierarchy based on their complexity.[11] Because complex priority arguments can be technical and difficult to follow, it has traditionally been considered desirable to prove results without priority arguments, or to see if results proved with priority arguments can also be proved without them. For example, Kummer published a paper on a proof for the existence of Friedberg numberings without using the priority method.

The lattice of computably enumerable sets

[edit]

When Post defined the notion of a simple set as a c.e. set with an infinite complement not containing any infinite c.e. set, he started to study the structure of the computably enumerable sets under inclusion. This lattice became a well-studied structure. Computable sets can be defined in this structure by the basic result that a set is computable if and only if the set and its complement are both computably enumerable. Infinite c.e. sets have always infinite computable subsets; but on the other hand, simple sets exist but do not always have a coinfinite computable superset. Post[14] introduced already hypersimple and hyperhypersimple sets; later maximal sets were constructed which are c.e. sets such that every c.e. superset is either a finite variant of the given maximal set or is co-finite. Post's original motivation in the study of this lattice was to find a structural notion such that every set which satisfies this property is neither in the Turing degree of the computable sets nor in the Turing degree of the halting problem. Post did not find such a property and the solution to his problem applied priority methods instead; in 1991, Harrington and Soare[18] found eventually such a property.

Automorphism problems

[edit]

Another important question is the existence of automorphisms in computability-theoretic structures. One of these structures is that one of computably enumerable sets under inclusion modulo finite difference; in this structure, A is below B if and only if the set difference B ? A is finite. Maximal sets (as defined in the previous paragraph) have the property that they cannot be automorphic to non-maximal sets, that is, if there is an automorphism of the computably enumerable sets under the structure just mentioned, then every maximal set is mapped to another maximal set. In 1974, Soare[19] showed that also the converse holds, that is, every two maximal sets are automorphic. So the maximal sets form an orbit, that is, every automorphism preserves maximality and any two maximal sets are transformed into each other by some automorphism. Harrington gave a further example of an automorphic property: that of the creative sets, the sets which are many-one equivalent to the halting problem.

Besides the lattice of computably enumerable sets, automorphisms are also studied for the structure of the Turing degrees of all sets as well as for the structure of the Turing degrees of c.e. sets. In both cases, Cooper claims to have constructed nontrivial automorphisms which map some degrees to other degrees; this construction has, however, not been verified and some colleagues believe that the construction contains errors and that the question of whether there is a nontrivial automorphism of the Turing degrees is still one of the main unsolved questions in this area.[20][16]

Kolmogorov complexity

[edit]

The field of Kolmogorov complexity and algorithmic randomness was developed during the 1960s and 1970s by Chaitin, Kolmogorov, Levin, Martin-L?f and Solomonoff (the names are given here in alphabetical order; much of the research was independent, and the unity of the concept of randomness was not understood at the time). The main idea is to consider a universal Turing machine U and to measure the complexity of a number (or string) x as the length of the shortest input p such that U(p) outputs x. This approach revolutionized earlier ways to determine when an infinite sequence (equivalently, characteristic function of a subset of the natural numbers) is random or not by invoking a notion of randomness for finite objects. Kolmogorov complexity became not only a subject of independent study but is also applied to other subjects as a tool for obtaining proofs. There are still many open problems in this area.[d]

Frequency computation

[edit]

This branch of computability theory analyzed the following question: For fixed m and n with 0 < m < n, for which functions A is it possible to compute for any different n inputs x1x2, ..., xn a tuple of n numbers y1, y2, ..., yn such that at least m of the equations A(xk) = yk are true. Such sets are known as (mn)-recursive sets. The first major result in this branch of computability theory is Trakhtenbrot's result that a set is computable if it is (mn)-recursive for some mn with 2m > n. On the other hand, Jockusch's semirecursive sets (which were already known informally before Jockusch introduced them 1968) are examples of a set which is (mn)-recursive if and only if 2m < n + 1. There are uncountably many of these sets and also some computably enumerable but noncomputable sets of this type. Later, Degtev established a hierarchy of computably enumerable sets that are (1, n + 1)-recursive but not (1, n)-recursive. After a long phase of research by Russian scientists, this subject became repopularized in the west by Beigel's thesis on bounded queries, which linked frequency computation to the above-mentioned bounded reducibilities and other related notions. One of the major results was Kummer's Cardinality Theory which states that a set A is computable if and only if there is an n such that some algorithm enumerates for each tuple of n different numbers up to n many possible choices of the cardinality of this set of n numbers intersected with A; these choices must contain the true cardinality but leave out at least one false one.

Inductive inference

[edit]

This is the computability-theoretic branch of learning theory. It is based on E. Mark Gold's model of learning in the limit from 1967 and has developed since then more and more models of learning. The general scenario is the following: Given a class S of computable functions, is there a learner (that is, computable functional) which outputs for any input of the form (f(0), f(1), ..., f(n)) a hypothesis. A learner M learns a function f if almost all hypotheses are the same index e of f with respect to a previously agreed on acceptable numbering of all computable functions; M learns S if M learns every f in S. Basic results are that all computably enumerable classes of functions are learnable while the class REC of all computable functions is not learnable. Many related models have been considered and also the learning of classes of computably enumerable sets from positive data is a topic studied from Gold's pioneering paper in 1967 onwards.

Generalizations of Turing computability

[edit]

Computability theory includes the study of generalized notions of this field such as arithmetic reducibility, hyperarithmetical reducibility and α-recursion theory, as described by Sacks in 1990.[21] These generalized notions include reducibilities that cannot be executed by Turing machines but are nevertheless natural generalizations of Turing reducibility. These studies include approaches to investigate the analytical hierarchy which differs from the arithmetical hierarchy by permitting quantification over sets of natural numbers in addition to quantification over individual numbers. These areas are linked to the theories of well-orderings and trees; for example the set of all indices of computable (nonbinary) trees without infinite branches is complete for level of the analytical hierarchy. Both Turing reducibility and hyperarithmetical reducibility are important in the field of effective descriptive set theory. The even more general notion of degrees of constructibility is studied in set theory.

Continuous computability theory

[edit]

Computability theory for digital computation is well developed. Computability theory is less well developed for analog computation that occurs in analog computers, analog signal processing, analog electronics, artificial neural networks and continuous-time control theory, modelled by differential equations and continuous dynamical systems.[22][23] For example, models of computation such as the Blum–Shub–Smale machine model have formalized computation on the reals.

Relationships between definability, proof and computability

[edit]

There are close relationships between the Turing degree of a set of natural numbers and the difficulty (in terms of the arithmetical hierarchy) of defining that set using a first-order formula. One such relationship is made precise by Post's theorem. A weaker relationship was demonstrated by Kurt G?del in the proofs of his completeness theorem and incompleteness theorems. G?del's proofs show that the set of logical consequences of an effective first-order theory is a computably enumerable set, and that if the theory is strong enough this set will be uncomputable. Similarly, Tarski's indefinability theorem can be interpreted both in terms of definability and in terms of computability.

Computability theory is also linked to second-order arithmetic, a formal theory of natural numbers and sets of natural numbers. The fact that certain sets are computable or relatively computable often implies that these sets can be defined in weak subsystems of second-order arithmetic. The program of reverse mathematics uses these subsystems to measure the non-computability inherent in well known mathematical theorems. In 1999, Simpson[17] discussed many aspects of second-order arithmetic and reverse mathematics.

The field of proof theory includes the study of second-order arithmetic and Peano arithmetic, as well as formal theories of the natural numbers weaker than Peano arithmetic. One method of classifying the strength of these weak systems is by characterizing which computable functions the system can prove to be total.[24] For example, in primitive recursive arithmetic any computable function that is provably total is actually primitive recursive, while Peano arithmetic proves that functions like the Ackermann function, which are not primitive recursive, are total. Not every total computable function is provably total in Peano arithmetic, however; an example of such a function is provided by Goodstein's theorem.

Name

[edit]

The field of mathematical logic dealing with computability and its generalizations has been called "recursion theory" since its early days. Robert I. Soare, a prominent researcher in the field, has proposed[12] that the field should be called "computability theory" instead. He argues that Turing's terminology using the word "computable" is more natural and more widely understood than the terminology using the word "recursive" introduced by Kleene. Many contemporary researchers have begun to use this alternate terminology.[e] These researchers also use terminology such as partial computable function and computably enumerable (c.e.) set instead of partial recursive function and recursively enumerable (r.e.) set. Not all researchers have been convinced, however, as explained by Fortnow[25] and Simpson.[26] Some commentators argue that both the names recursion theory and computability theory fail to convey the fact that most of the objects studied in computability theory are not computable.[27]

In 1967, Rogers[28] has suggested that a key property of computability theory is that its results and structures should be invariant under computable bijections on the natural numbers (this suggestion draws on the ideas of the Erlangen program in geometry). The idea is that a computable bijection merely renames numbers in a set, rather than indicating any structure in the set, much as a rotation of the Euclidean plane does not change any geometric aspect of lines drawn on it. Since any two infinite computable sets are linked by a computable bijection, this proposal identifies all the infinite computable sets (the finite computable sets are viewed as trivial). According to Rogers, the sets of interest in computability theory are the noncomputable sets, partitioned into equivalence classes by computable bijections of the natural numbers.

Professional organizations

[edit]

The main professional organization for computability theory is the Association for Symbolic Logic, which holds several research conferences each year. The interdisciplinary research Association Computability in Europe (CiE) also organizes a series of annual conferences.

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ The Handbook of Recursive Mathematics[1] covers many of the known results in this field.
  2. ^ Many of these foundational papers are collected in The Undecidable (1965) edited by Martin Davis
  3. ^ The list of undecidable problems gives additional examples.
  4. ^ A list of open problems is maintained by Joseph Miller and André Nies, the André Nies's homepage has it published.
  5. ^ MathSciNet searches for the titles like "computably enumerable" and "c.e." show that many papers have been published with this terminology as well as with the other one.

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Ershov, Yury Leonidovich; Goncharov, Sergei Savostyanovich [at Wikidata]; Nerode, Anil; Remmel, Jeffrey B. (1998). Handbook of Recursive Mathematics. North-Holland. ISBN 0-7204-2285-X.
  2. ^ Radó, Tibor (May 1962). "On non-computable functions". Bell System Technical Journal. 41 (3): 877–884. doi:10.1002/j.1538-7305.1962.tb00480.x.
  3. ^ Soare, Robert Irving (2025-08-05). "Computability Theory and Applications: The Art of Classical Computability" (PDF). Department of Mathematics. University of Chicago. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2025-08-05. Retrieved 2025-08-05.
  4. ^ a b Kleene, Stephen Cole (1952). Introduction to Metamathematics. North-Holland. pp. 300, 376.
  5. ^ a b Davis, Martin, ed. (2004) [1965]. The Undecidable: Basic Papers on Undecidable Propositions, Unsolvable Problems and Computable Functions. Dover Publications, Inc. p. 84. ISBN 978-0-486-43228-1. p. 84: Kurt G?del (1946): Tarski has stressed in his lecture (and I think justly) the great importance of the concept of general recursiveness (or Turing's computability). It seems to me that this importance is largely due to the fact that with this concept one has for the first time succeeded in giving an absolute notion to an interesting epistemological notion, i.e., one not depending on the formalism chosen.
  6. ^ G?del, Kurt (1990). "[G?del (1946)]". In Feferman, Solomon; et al. (eds.). Kurt G?del Publications 1938–1974 Volume II. Vol. II. New York, USA: Oxford University Press. pp. 144ff. ISBN 978-0-19-514721-6. p. 150: To be more precise: a function of integers is computable in any formal system containing arithmetic if and only if it is computable in arithmetic, where a function f is called computable in S if there is in S a computable term representing f. (NB. This volume also includes the 1946 paper by Kurt G?del (with commentary by Charles Parsons at pp. 144ff.). This 1990 edition has the cited footnote added by G?del on p. 150 (which had also been added to G?del's reprint in Davis' 1965 compilation).)
  7. ^ Church, Alonzo (1936a). "An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory". American Journal of Mathematics. 58 (2): 345–363. doi:10.2307/2371045. JSTOR 2371045. Reprinted in Davis 1965.
  8. ^ Church, Alonzo (1936b). "A note on the Entscheidungsproblem". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 1 (1): 40–41. doi:10.2307/2269326. JSTOR 2269326. S2CID 42323521. Reprinted in Davis 1965.
  9. ^ a b Turing, Alan Mathison (1937) [1936]. "On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem". Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society. 2. 42 (1): 230–265. doi:10.1112/plms/s2-42.1.230. S2CID 73712. Turing, Alan Mathison (1938). "On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem. A Correction" (PDF). Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society. 2. 43 (1): 544–546. doi:10.1112/plms/s2-43.6.544. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2025-08-05. Retrieved 2025-08-05. Reprinted in Davis 1965.
  10. ^ Cutland, Nigel J. (1980). Computability, An introduction to recursive function theory. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-29465-7.
  11. ^ a b Soare, Robert Irving (1987). Recursively Enumerable Sets and Degrees. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Springer-Verlag. ISBN 0-387-15299-7.
  12. ^ a b Soare, Robert Irving (1996). "Computability and recursion" (PDF). Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 2 (3): 284–321. doi:10.2307/420992. JSTOR 420992. S2CID 5894394.
  13. ^ Turing, Alan Mathison (1939). "Systems of logic based on ordinals". Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society. 2. 45 (1): 161–228. doi:10.1112/plms/s2-45.1.161. hdl:21.11116/0000-0001-91CE-3. Reprinted in Davis 1965.
  14. ^ a b c Post, Emil Leon (1944). "Recursively enumerable sets of positive integers and their decision problems". Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. 50 (5): 284–316. doi:10.1090/S0002-9904-1944-08111-1. MR 0010514. Reprinted in Davis 1965.
  15. ^ Shore, Richard Arnold; Slaman, Theodore Allen (1999). "Defining the Turing Jump". Mathematical Research Letters. 6 (6): 711–722. doi:10.4310/mrl.1999.v6.n6.a10. ISSN 1073-2780. MR 1739227.
  16. ^ a b Ambos-Spies, Klaus; Fejer, Peter A. (2014). "Degrees of unsolvability" (PDF). In Siekmann, J?rg H. (ed.). Computational Logic. Handbook of the History of Logic. Vol. 9. Amsterdam: Elsevier/North-Holland. pp. 443–494. doi:10.1016/B978-0-444-51624-4.50010-1. ISBN 978-0-444-51624-4. MR 3362163. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2025-08-05.
  17. ^ a b Simpson, Steven George (1999). Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic. Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-64882-8.
  18. ^ Harrington, Leo Anthony; Soare, Robert Irving (1991). "Post's Program and incomplete recursively enumerable sets". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA. 88 (22): 10242–10246. Bibcode:1991PNAS...8810242H. doi:10.1073/pnas.88.22.10242. PMC 52904. PMID 11607241.
  19. ^ Soare, Robert Irving (1974). "Automorphisms of the lattice of recursively enumerable sets, Part I: Maximal sets". Annals of Mathematics. 100 (1): 80–120. doi:10.2307/1970842. JSTOR 1970842.
  20. ^ Slaman, Theodore Allen; Woodin, William Hugh (1986). "Definability in the Turing degrees". Illinois Journal of Mathematics. 30 (2): 320–334. doi:10.1215/ijm/1256044641. MR 0840131.
  21. ^ Sacks, Gerald Enoch (1990). Higher Recursion Theory. Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-19305-7.
  22. ^ Orponen, Pekka (1997). "A Survey of Continuous-Time Computation Theory". Advances in Algorithms, Languages, and Complexity. pp. 209–224. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.53.1991. doi:10.1007/978-1-4613-3394-4_11. ISBN 978-1-4613-3396-8.
  23. ^ Moore, Cris (1996). "Recursion theory on the reals and continuous-time computation". Theoretical Computer Science. 162 (1): 23–44. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.6.5519. doi:10.1016/0304-3975(95)00248-0.
  24. ^ Fairtlough, Matt; Wainer, Stanley S. (1998). "Hierarchies of Provably Recursive Functions". In Buss, Samuel R. (ed.). Handbook of Proof Theory. Elsevier. pp. 149–208. ISBN 978-0-08-053318-6.
  25. ^ Fortnow, Lance Jeremy (2025-08-05). "Is it Recursive, Computable or Decidable?". Archived from the original on 2025-08-05. Retrieved 2025-08-05.
  26. ^ Simpson, Stephen George (2025-08-05). "What is computability theory?". FOM email list. Archived from the original on 2025-08-05. Retrieved 2025-08-05.
  27. ^ Friedman, Harvey (2025-08-05). "Renaming recursion theory". FOM email list. Archived from the original on 2025-08-05. Retrieved 2025-08-05.
  28. ^ Rogers, Hartley Jr. (1987). The Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability (2nd ed.). MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-68052-1.

Further reading

[edit]
Undergraduate level texts
Advanced texts
Survey papers and collections
Research papers and collections
[edit]
750是什么材质 流产可以吃什么水果 o型血吃什么瘦的最快 减脂吃什么蔬菜 卵黄囊是什么意思
下一年是什么生肖 cnv是什么意思 利是什么生肖 防字代表什么生肖 瑕疵是什么意思
等闲之辈是什么意思 阴道干涩用什么药 直肠给药对小孩身体有什么影响 什么是权力 cta是什么意思
万条垂下绿丝绦是什么季节 胃镜预约挂什么科 晨对什么 外阴起红点是什么病 皮赘是什么原因引起的
排卵期出血是什么原因造成的hcv7jop7ns0r.cn 胃阴虚吃什么中成药hcv7jop7ns2r.cn 有心无力是什么意思hcv9jop0ns9r.cn 情绪上来像发疯一般是什么病hcv8jop2ns8r.cn 酸梅汤不适合什么人喝tiangongnft.com
泉州有什么特产hcv8jop8ns1r.cn 扑朔迷离是什么意思hcv7jop5ns5r.cn 肽是什么hcv8jop5ns7r.cn 鱼香肉丝为什么叫鱼香肉丝hcv9jop5ns7r.cn 黄瓜吃多了有什么坏处zsyouku.com
香草是什么hcv9jop5ns1r.cn 经期为什么不能拔牙hcv9jop3ns3r.cn 胬肉是什么hcv9jop6ns5r.cn 什么的杏花hcv9jop0ns6r.cn 平顶山为什么叫平顶山hcv7jop9ns8r.cn
心衰吃什么恢复的快hcv7jop5ns6r.cn 程门立雪是什么生肖hcv9jop3ns9r.cn 月经前几天是什么期hcv7jop5ns3r.cn 茯苓不能和什么一起吃hcv8jop5ns6r.cn 扬州有什么特产naasee.com
百度